And an Ordered Field That Can Be Ordered in More Than One Way
Study Help for Baby Rudin, Part 1.2

The set of real numbers
is more than just a set. As we learn at a young age, we can visualize the real numbers using the real number line, implicitly implying that they are “ordered”. The real numbers also have the algebraic structure of a mathematical field, in which we can add and multiply according to the usual rules. In fact, the real numbers form an ordered field.
The set of real numbers has a field structure, under the operations of ordinary addition and ordinary multiplication. The set of real numbers is also a totally ordered set. Taken together, these facts are almost enough to mean the real numbers form an ordered field.
However, we cannot impose a (total) order on the real number field in any way we want. In order to be an ordered field, the algebraic field properties and the order must be “compatible” in certain special ways.
What are these ways?
- If the same number is added to both sides of an inequality, then the inequality symbol, either
or
, should stay in the same direction. That is, if
, then
.
- The product of two positive numbers should be positive. That is, if
and
, then
.
The number zero plays a special role in defining which numbers are positive and which numbers are negative to begin with. Many textbooks in Real Analysis approach this topic axiomatically. They assume that the set of positive real numbers are, in part, characterized by the property that
.
Where Are These Topics Found in Baby Rudin?
In “Principles of Mathematical Analysis”, Third Edition, by Walter Rudin (a.k.a., Baby Rudin), these topics are addressed on pages 3-8. Also found on these pages is the crucial concept that the ordered field of real numbers is complete. I will discuss this topic in-depth in later posts. It is the key feature that distinguishes the real numbers from, for example, the rational numbers.
While Baby Rudin takes a very precise approach to many of the topics in Real Analysis, for the concept of an ordered set, it is less precise than many other texts. In order to open your mind to other possibilities and help you realize when definitions are not as precise as they could be, it will be useful for us to consider the precise definition of an ordered set in this article.
Definition of an Order on a Set and an Ordered Set
Suppose represents a nonempty set. In Baby Rudin, an order on
is defined to be a (binary) relation, denoted by
, with two properties:
- If
and
, then one and only one of the statements
is true (“trichotomy”). This also means that any two distinct elements are “comparable” (contrast this with the concept of a partially ordered set, or “poset”).
- If
, and if
and
, then
(“transitivity”).
In addition, Baby Rudin defines to mean either
or
. Furthermore,
is another way to write
and
is another way to write
.
A set is called an ordered set if an order is defined on it.
So What is Wrong With This Definition of an Order on a Set?
You might wonder: what is wrong with this definition? Why is it not precise?
The main reason it is not precise is that the notion of a (binary) relation on a set has not been defined. In addition, we are understanding the word “set” from the perspective of “naive set theory”. Naive set theory has its own problems, which we will not get into (it leads to paradoxes).
Most textbooks in Real Analysis wisely avoid trying to “fix” naive set theory. That is, they avoid approaching it from an axiomatic point of view. However, it is probably worthwhile to at least define the concept of a relation here. This is based on the naive view of a set as a collection of “objects” (whatever those objects might be).
Cartesian Products, Relations, and Orders
We need a preliminary concept. Given any two sets and
, we define the Cartesian product
of
and
to be the set of all ordered pairs
. Note that the first “coordinate” of
must be from the set
and the second “coordinate” of
must be from the set
. Also note that, if
, then
(they are different sets).
Definition: A (binary) relation on a set
is a subset of the Cartesian product
. When
, it is common to also write
(i.e., “
is related to
“).
That’s it! A relation on a set is just a subset of the Cartesian product of the set with itself. (I will avoid including the word “binary” from now on; evidently, there are other kinds of relations that can be defined on a set as well.)
So what, then, is an order on a set
? It’s a special kind of relation on
.
Definition: An order on a set is a relation
on
that also satisfies the following properties: 1) If
, then one and only one of the statements
or
is true (“trichotomy”). And 2) If
and if
and
, then
(“transitivity”).
From now on, we write in place of
for an order on
. In other words, technically-speaking, the symbol
represents a special kind of subset of
. Also note how this definition jibes with the definition in Baby Rudin written further above.
Example 1: An Order on a Finite Set
It is probably best at this point to give a simple example. Let . Define an order
on
to be the set:
(i.e,
equals this 3 element set)
Note that is certainly a subset of
. You should check that the definition of an order is satisfied by the set
here.
As sets, and
can be visualized as points in a “plane”, where the elements of
are on the “axes”.
Do not take this too literally because ,
, and
might not be numbers. However, it can still be a helpful tool for our imaginations.

We can also visualize this ordered set as three points on a “line” (i.e., vertices on a linear “directed graph”), as shown in the picture at the very top of this post. The directed line segments themselves are not part of the set — they only indicate the direction of the ordering ( is less than
is less than
).
Based on this order on , it would also make sense to write
(i.e,
equals this 6 element set)
Don’t let it bother you that the letters in this set are just pure symbols. We don’t have to think of about orders in terms of relations between numbers. For example, the letters could represent foods that you want to eat at a meal, while the order could represent the order you want to eat them in.
We can also define other orders on . Another example is
. In fact, there are
distinct (total) orders that can be defined on any set with 3 elements.
Ordered Fields
In a nutshell, a nonempty set is called a field if there are two binary operations defined of
, typically called addition
and multiplication
(or
), such that all the “standard” properties you learn in school hold true for these operations (closure, associativity, commutativity, etc…). The most common fields encountered by students in school are the rational numbers
, the real numbers
, and the complex numbers
(under the “standard” definitions of addition and multiplication). We could give a full list of all the field properties here, but we will save that for another post.
Are there any finite fields? There most certainly are.
Example 2: a Field with Two Elements
The simplest finite field is the two-element set . In this field, we define addition by the equations
and
. We define multiplication by the equations
and
. These operations are called “mod 2 arithmetic”.
There are two possible orders on . The most “natural” one is
(That’s it! This is a one-element subset of the Cartesian product
). This means that
.
However, now we ask whether this order is “compatible” with the field properties as discussed at the beginning of this article. That is, if the same element is added to both sides of a valid inequality, does the inequality stay the same “direction”?
The answer is no. Note that , but
because
(i.e.,
).
This is a partial argument for why cannot be defined to be an ordered field (though it certainly can be defined to be an ordered set). In fact, no finite field can be an ordered field.
Example 3: the Rational Numbers Form an Ordered Field
Since each rational number is a real number, each rational number corresponds to a unique point on a real number line. It therefore seems natural to hope that the “standard” order on , “imposed” on
, will make
into an ordered field. Since we need to have some starting point, we will assume that we know what it means for an arbitrary integer (element of the “ring”
) to be positive or negative or zero.
Given two distinct rational numbers , say in lowest terms with
and
taken to be positive integers, how should we determine the truth value (true or false) of the statement
?
It seems reasonable to define that if and
, or if
and
, then
, so we do so. Note that this also means that
if and only if
, and that
if and only if
.
But what if and
are either both positive or both negative? Think about it in terms of “cross-multiplication”. We should define
if and only if
(the inequality should not change direction after multiplying since each integer is positive). But this is true if and only if
. This last inequality on the integers will be how we define
to be true when
and
are both positive. In other words, in this case, we say that
if and only if
.
The case where and
are both negative is handled with the same inequality, namely
. The reason is that after “cross-multiplying” by two negative integers, the inequality should still end up in the same direction.
Is This Order Compatible with the Field Properties?
Now we ask: is this ordering compatible with the field properties? Once again, we assume we know all about how arithmetic and inequalities work in the ring . We also assume we know how to add and multiply rational numbers.
Certainly the product of two positive rational numbers is positive. If and
, then
. This is because the product of two positive integers is known to be positive.
For the other condition, let’s just consider the case where all the rational numbers (and all the integers) involved are positive. You can consider the other cases on your own.
Assume that and that
with
(also,
). We want to prove that
.
Our assumption implies that . By the definition of addition in
, we can write
and
. This means we want to prove that
.
But this is easy. We can compute . But
and
. Therefore,
so that
.
Actually, this argument works with no restrictions on and
as long as we don’t divide by zero to form the fraction
.
the real numbers form an Ordered field
For the moment, we will not define the “standard” order on the field of real numbers that makes it an ordered field. In fact, we are also not defining how to add and multiply real numbers at the moment either.
But here’s a question. Is there only one order we can define on to make it an ordered field? The answer is “yes”, with a mild caveat. It is true “up to (order-preserving) isomorphism”. See https://math.ucr.edu/~res/math205A/uniqreals.pdf for more detail. Suffice it to say that we will take the answer to be “yes”.
Definition of an Ordered Field
Here is a formal definition of an ordered field which is equivalent to the definition given on page 7 of Baby Rudin. For this article, we are still not fully defining what a field is.
Definition: Let be a field. We say that
is an ordered field if it is an ordered set (with order
) and the following conditions are true. (i) If
and
, then
. (ii) If
with
and
, then
.
As stated above, the ordering on the real number field is essentially unique. But we might wonder. Do there exist other ordered fields which have two distinct (non-isomorphic) compatible orders?
An Ordered Field with Two Distinct Compatible Orders
You should always strive to be familiar with many “counterexamples” in a subject like Real Analysis. A counterexample is an example that disproves a mathematical statement. In other words, a counterexample is an example that shows that a given (necessarily false) statement is indeed false. Oftentimes the false statement might, at first glance, “seem” to be true. That’s what makes counterexamples a truly necessary part of your education in mathematics. They can correct faulty intuition and show you where you need to be more careful.
Here’s a simple example of a false statement that might seem to be true at first glance: if , then
. This is indeed a false statement: the number
is a counterexample.
If you really want to understand Real Analysis deeply, I highly recommend getting the book “Counterexamples in Analysis”, by Bernard Gelbaum and John Olmsted. On page 14 of that book you will find an example of a field that is an ordered field in two distinct ways. Let’s explore this example now.
Example 4: The Rationals with the square root of 2 adjoined
Let (note that I’m not bothering to write
and
as fractions). This set is indeed a field under ordinary addition and multiplication. It is often informally described as “the rationals adjoined with the square root of 2”. It is the “smallest” field extension of
containing the number
.
In , we add and multiply numbers as you would expect:
and
. It is important to also note that every nonzero element in
has a multiplicative inverse that is also in
. To see this, note that
, where
since
with either
or
, and since
.
The standard way to define an order is to use the order it inherits as a subfield of the real numbers
. This amounts to defining
if and only if
.
However, there is another (non-isomorphic) order, call it , that can be defined on
. We define
if and only if
, where
represents the standard order (written in the opposite direction) on
(and on
). Note the subtle difference between the definitions of
and
.
We should check that is still an ordered field with respect to
.
Check Condition (i)
Let and assume that
. We want to show that
.
The fact that implies that
. Since
and
, we must show that
.
But this is easy: . Therefore, condition (i) is satisfied.
Check Condition (ii)
Now assume and that
and
. We want to prove that
.
The facts that and
imply that
and
. Since
, we must show that
.
But this is easy as well: it follows because and because
. Therefore, condition (ii) is satisfied.
Can This Order Be Visualized?
You might wonder: can this order on
be visualized?
First of all, we should realize that, even though is a subset of the real number line, if we want, we can visualize
as being a subset of the “rational coordinate plane”
(the
symbols represent Cartesian products, as defined further above).
How? It’s analogous to how complex numbers can be visualized in the complex plane. Associate each number with the point
(with rational coordinates). In other words, we could think of the horizontal axis as the “rational axis” (as a subset of the real
-axis) and the vertical axis as the “irrational axis” (as a subset of the real
-axis). The “rational part” of
would then be
, while the “irrational part” of
would then be
(just as the imaginary part of a complex number is a real number).
Though this might seem strange, it is actually a very natural thing to do. If you’re interested, it also turns out that this association is “structure-preserving” in that it defines an isomorphism of vector spaces over the field .
Visualizing the Standard Order
Since the condition is equivalent to
, the (linear) transformation
defined by
maps all the points in
above the line
to the positive horizontal axis and all the points in
below the line
to the negative horizontal axis. In other words, in
, the “positives” with respect to
are above that line and the “negatives” with respect to
are below that line. The only point of
that is actually on the line
is the origin
, which gets mapped to itself.
As a mapping from to the
(part of the horizontal axis), the function
is not only onto, but is also one-to-one. It is also clear that
.
We can picture this as shown below. Note that the transformation maps points to the horizontal axis parallel to the line . This means that the points end up the same (signed) horizontal distance from the line
that they started with. This horizontal signed distance, even at the start, is the true “numerical value” of
(as a rational number when
and an irrational number when
).

Visualizing the Non-Standard Order
For the non-standard order , we can still visualize
as a plane in the same way, through the association
. However, the locations of the positive and negative points changes (because the positive and negative numbers themselves change) as well as how the points get mapped to on the horizontal axis. This then changes where we imagine the positive and negative numbers of
to “live” as a subset of the real line
.
The condition is equivalent to
, which is equivalent to
. Therefore, the (linear) transformation
defined by
maps all the points in
below the line
to the positive horizontal axis and all the points in
above the line
to the negative horizontal axis. In other words, in
, the “positives” with respect to
are below that line and the “negatives” with respect to
are above that line. As before, the origin
is the only point in
on the line itself and it gets mapped to itself.
As before, as a mapping from to the
(part of the horizontal axis), the function
is not only onto, but is also one-to-one. It is also clear that
.
We can picture this as shown below. Note that the transformation maps points to the horizontal axis parallel to the line . This means that the points end up the same (signed) horizontal distance from the line
that they started with. This horizontal signed distance, even at the start, is the true “numerical value” of
(as a rational number when
and an irrational number when
).

Numbers That Are Positive With Respect to Both Orders
There are certainly numbers in that are positive with respect to both orders. Visually, these are the numbers that are in the intersection of the blue regions from both figures above. In other words, these are the numbers corresponding to points
in the wedge where
and
. There are also, of course, numbers that will be negative with respect to both orders.
Relating the Visuals
How should we relate these visuals? In other words, if we imagine a point as being on the real line (i.e., being in the set
) with respect to the standard order
, where will it be with respect to the new order
?
We can think about this in terms of the transformations and
. Start with a number
. With respect to the standard order
, we initially visualize this as the point
. We then compute
(map it away from the horizontal axis and parallel to the line
). From there, we find
(map it back to the horizontal axis and parallel to the line
.
What is the net effect of this composition? It maps to
.
However, the geometric effect of this composition is not very clear, because it depends on the values of both and
. Two numbers in
could be “close together” under
but relatively “far apart” under
.
For example, and
are close together (within about 0.05 units) under
. But
and
are relatively far apart (about 9.95 units) under
.
This means it is tough to tell where a point will end up under the composition of these transformations just by looking at its initial location on the number line. You really do need to know the values of and
in the expression
.
On the other hand, if you increase or decrease the numerical value of just by changing either the rational part
alone or the irrational part
alone (don’t change them both at the same time), then it is easier to see what will happen. Increasing
alone will make the number larger with respect to both
and
. Increasing
alone will make the number larger with respect to
, but smaller with respect to
.
In the end, the points do indeed get “mixed up” under the composition. It is definitely difficult to fully visualize.
You might ask: what happens to the other real numbers that are not in in this visual? The happy answer is that you don’t need to worry about them. This visual is for
alone. You can effectively just pretend the other real numbers don’t exist in the final visualizations described above.
Bonus Material: Relationship to Field Extensions and Galois Theory
If you know about field extensions and Galois theory, you should recognize the mapping defined by
as being a nontrivial element of the Galois group
(of the field extension
over
). In fact, it is the only nontrivial element of the Galois group. In other words,
is isomorphic to the additive group
.
But even though is an isomorphism of
to itself (also called an automorphism of
), what we have just seen above is that
does not preserve the order structure of
as an ordered field. It is not an “ordered field isomorphism”.
For example, , but
The relation can also be defined in terms of
. In fact, we can say that
if and only if
.
Evidently, something similar will happen for any field extension of of the form
, where
is a positive integer which is not a perfect square.
Thank you for the nice Post Prof. Kinney. Great to read the second post!
I have some questions.
1. L<* is not isomorphic to L< right? Eventhough L<* by itself is an isomorphism from Q2 to R2 .?
2. \alpha does not preserve the order structure of \Bbb{Q}(\sqrt{2}) as an ordered field, with it's original order meaning that for x<y the following is flase: \alpha(x) , but in theory one can define it’s own order relation in such a case one could make \alpha ordered w.r.t. the order i.e. L*<?
Many thanks. Best regards,
Diego.
The L<* and L< are just mappings. They can be thought of as isomorphisms of Q x Q and Q(sqrt(2)) as vector spaces over Q. I'm not quite sure what you are asking on #2. I need to rewrite the blog post at the end to make it more clear, but a + b*sqrt(2) *> 0 if and only if alpha(a + b*sqrt(2)) = a – b*sqrt(2) > 0.
Something happened with the post, when uploading. Sorry about that. I meant that, these doesn’t hold: alpha (x)<alpha (y), x and y in Q(sqrt(2)). But the order doesn’t hold anymore. But one could still find an order relation for the results of alpha?
I’m sorry. I’m still not sure what you are asking. Are you asking if alpha can be used to define an order?
Sorry, I was very unclear. ” Alpha doesn’t preserve the order structure of Q(sqrt(2)) for the relation >”. Can I explain it in the following way?: -Because the relation > doesn’t hold anymore after alpha is applied to Q(sqrt(2)). Furthermore, I think you explained this in the youtube video, that alpha doesn’t preserve the order, doesn’t necessarily mean that a new relation can’t be found to define a new order for Q(sqrt(2)) for alpha.
Actually it turns out, I don’t know how to you call the set of elements that result from the map alpha? alpha (Q(sqrt(2))?
Thank you much.